Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

24/7 Homework Help

Stuck on a homework question? Our verified tutors can answer all questions, from basic math to advanced rocket science!

Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

ORDER NOW FOR CUSTOMIZED, PLAGIARISM-FREE PAPERS

Instructions: Psychology has had a problematic relationship regarding its status and recognition as a “Science”, and part of the problem has to do with how we perceive and value what is scientific (and what is not scientific). In this sense, the problem goes beyond affirming that Psychology is (or isn’t ) a Science. Taking this into consideration elaborate an argument that discusses one (1) of the following: Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

A) Discuss the debate regarding concept of “paradigm” and its relationship to Psychology (as a discipline and form of knowledge), taking into consideration how this influences how we view Psychology as a Science (and what kind or type of science). Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

B) Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Word format, a letter size twelve (12) and a spacing of one and a half (1.5) between sentences (or line spacing in the paragraph options). The extension of the work should not be less than three (3) pages or greater than five (5) pages of content (not title page or cover of any kind is required).

  • attachmenthergenhahn___henley_2014._introduction..pdf
  • attachmentleahey_mythical_revolution_american_psychology.pdf
  • attachmentsantiago_relevance_of_vygotskys_developmental_perspective_to_the_debate_on_methodology.pdf
  • attachmentskinner_why_i_am_not_a_cognitive_psychologist_1977.pdf
  • attachmentsternberg_unified_psychology.pdf
  • attachmentteo_functions_of_knowledge_in_psychology.pdf

Questions of Psychology’s Evolution

The Mythical Revolutions of American Psychology Thomas H. Leahey Virginia Commonwealth University

The history of experimental psychology in America is typ- ically told as a series of two Kuhnian revolutions sepa- rating three periods of normal science dominated by the mentalist, then behaviorist, and finally today’s cognitivist paradigm. Models of revolution developed by T. S. Kuhn, I. B. Cohen, and R. Porter are described and used to for- mulate questions and criteria for investigating revolutions in experimental psychology. The history of the behaviorist and cognitivist “revolutions” as seen by contemporaries shows that each was in fact a period of rapid but contin- uous and nonrevolutionary change. An alternative, nar- rative framework for telling psychology’s story is suggested in terms of guiding themata and the progressive devel- opment of four research traditions: representationalist, realist, connectionist, and reductionist.

How shall the story of psychology be told? At the centen- nial of the American Psychological Association (APA), American psychology finds itself divided into bitterly quarreling factions exchanging charges of bad faith. The way our history is told has helped create and maintain divisions within our discipline. For the guiding myth of American psychology is a story of conflict and struggle, dominance and revolution.

There is a story of the development of American psychology widely told and widely repeated. In the be- ginning—1879—psychology was born as the science of mental life, studying consciousness with introspection. Then, in 1913, the dominance of mentalism was chal- lenged and shattered by the rude and simplistic behav- iorists, who made a revolution against the ancien regime mentalists. They slew the science of mental life and re- placed it with the science of behavior, creating a decades- long rule of behavior study and behavior theory. However, in 1956, a new revolution began, its makers waving the banner of cognition, aided by outside forces from lin- guistics and artificial intelligence. After two decades of struggle, the ancien regime of behaviorism was defeated, or at least repressed, and the rule of information-pro- cessing cognitive psychology began. Today, we stand per- haps on the threshold of a new revolution, as the young warriors of connectionism challenge the aging stalwarts of information processing (Bechtel & Abrahamsen, 1990; Schneider, 1987; Tienson, 1991).

It is an exciting story, full of sound and fury, but

what does it signify? Is it true? I hope to show that the romantic drama of revolution in the history of American psychology is a plausible but dangerous myth, and to sug- gest a better story, of developing traditions.

Revolutions Despite its dubious ancestry, the word “revolution” by now has a Pavlovian effect on some historians: applied to any event, it leads at once to eager expectations of radical structural change, profound discontinuity, a sweeping away of the old order. (Clark, 1986, p. 38)

The Concept of Revolution

The nature of revolutions has received a great deal of attention over the last few decades in history and political science (Brinton, 1952; Clark, 1986; Porter &Teich, 1986; Paynton & Blackey, 1971) and more recently in history of science (Cohen, 1985; Kuhn, 1957, 1962/1970; Porter, 1986). Although revolutions were once seen as rare in- terruptions in the natural course of human history, they have come to be regarded as frequent, even commonplace, events (Clark, 1986; Porter, 1986).

It is interesting that the term revolution did not orig- inate in politics, but in science (Griewank, 1969/1971). The term arose in astronomy to describe the circular movement of objects through the heavens, and via as- trology came to be applied to history. Galileo wrote, “The revolutions of the globe we inhabit give rise to the mishaps and accidents of human existence” (cited in Griewank, p. 17). The new image of celestial rotations reinforced older beliefs in the wheel of fortune governing human lives, raising them up to power, fame, and fortune, and then inevitably smashing them down again (Cohen, 1985).

The first metaphorical application of the concept of astronomical revolution to political revolution was ex- pressed by Polybius (200-118 B.C.): “Such is the cycle of political revolutions, the course appointed by nature in which constitutions change, disappear and finally re- turn to the point from which they started” (cited in Cohen, 1985, p. 54). Polybius’s conception of revolutions was conservative, a circular movement of return rather than a forward leap in linear progress. Thus, into the early modern period, the term revolution was generally

Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Thomas H. Leahey, Department of Psychology, Virginia Commonwealth Uni- versity, Richmond, VA 23284-2018.

308 February 1992 • American Psychologist Copyright 1992 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. O0O3-O66X/92/S2.0O

Vol. 47, No. 2, 308-318

applied to restorations of an older order that had been disturbed by rebellion or corruption.

Nevertheless, the circular concept of historical rev- olutions also contained the idea of a revolution as a violent overturning (Cohen, 1985), and during the 17th century, the meaning of revolution gradually lost its cyclic com- ponent and acquired its now-familiar sense of a sharp, fundamental, and improving break with the past (Grie- wank, 1969/1971).

The first political change to be described by contem- poraries in this new sense was the Glorious Revolution of 1688, and during the 18th century, the idea of revo- lutions as decisively progressive leaps permanently re- placed the older conservative notion (Cohen, 1985; Porter, 1986). Behind the changing conception of political rev- olutions from cyclic to progressive overturnings lay the concept of revolutions in science (Porter, 1986). Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Revolutions in Science

In the first declaration of revolution in the history of sci- ence, Bernard de Fontenelle (1657-1757) declared in the early 1700s that the invention of the calculus had con- stituted a revolution in mathematics. A little later, An- toine Lavoisier (1743-1794) declared in 1733 that his research constituted a revolution in chemistry (Cohen, 1985). The view of revolutions advanced by Fontenelle and Lavoisier developed the idea that revolutions were progressive breaks with the past, a view advanced with fervor by the Enlightenment philosophes, who linked their French Revolution—and revolutions yet to come—to progressive leaps in science (Porter, 1986). Because they are at once romantically dramatic and daringly progres- sive, many scientists (and historians) have dubbed as rev- olutionary almost any new idea, until “our dominant im- age of the history of science [and history tout court; (Clark, 1986)] is bursting at the seams with revolutions” (Porter, p. 291).

Not all change or even innovation is revolutionary, no matter that revolutionary talk satisfies our eager ex- pectations. If one is to weigh properly the thesis that psy- chology has experienced revolutions, one must be guided by models of revolution and criteria of revolutionary change. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Models of Revolution in Science

Thomas S. Kuhn

Thomas S. Kuhn, through his study of the Copernican Revolution (Kuhn, 1957) and his subsequent general analysis of revolutions in science, The Structure of Sci- entific Revolutions (Kuhn, 1962/1970), has done more than anyone else to popularize the idea of scientific rev- olution. Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions has been widely influential not only in history and phi- losophy of science (Gutting, 1980; Hacking, 1981), but also in psychology (Coleman & Salamon, 1988). Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Kuhn is heir to a tradition in history of science begun by Alexandre Koyre, which created the idea of scientific eras controlled by guiding weltanschauungen (Kuhn’s

paradigms) and, in consequence, the idea of scientific change as involving changes in weltanschauungen, as “putting on a new pair of spectacles” (Kuhn’s gestalt switch). Koyre and his followers also created the histo- riographical event of the Scientific Revolution itself (Porter, 1986). Although Fontenelle and Lavoisier (and others since) had spoken of revolutions in science, it was not until 1939 that, beginning with Koyre, anyone spoke of the Scientific Revolution. Once minted, the term be- came common currency and now seems as old as the Scientific Revolution itself.

Kuhn (1962/1970) brought the Koyrean lineaments of the Scientific Revolution to his picture of later revo- lutions in science. The Scientific Revolution was an event of high drama, in which great thinkers had great thoughts and defeated the entrenched forces of superstition and ignorance. It “outshines everything since the rise of Christianity and reduces the Renaissance and Reforma- tion to the rank of mere episodes” (Butterfield, 1949/ 1957, p. 7). Similarly, Kuhn depicted revolutions in sci- ence as smaller dramas with crisis and conflict, the clash of ideas, and the overturning of one worldview by another. It is hardly surprising that, to Kuhn’s own chagrin, most of the attention his book received focused on revolution- ary change, not normal science. Next to the revolution makers, normal scientists seem pathetic, puny souls (Lakatos & Musgrave, 1970). And it is no wonder that, after 1962, scientists should want to make (and see) rev- olutions in their own work and time.

Kuhn (1962/1970) proposed that any particular sci- ence begins in a preparadigm stage, during which several weltanschauungen attempt to define and dominate the field. At some point, one Weltanschauung’s way of con- ducting the science becomes definitive, and it becomes a controlling paradigm, as the other soi-disant paradigms fall into desuetude or are stigmatized as pseudoscientific. Thus, in the Scientific Revolution, Newton’s achievement in the Principia defined classical physics, and the rival Cartesian viewpoint faded away. Control of a field by a single paradigm marks the maturing of a field into a gen- uine science, and the cycle of normal science and revo- lutionary science begins.

Kuhn (1962/1970) described scientific revolutions as passing through four stages.

1. Normal science. During this phase, ordinary sci- entific research and scientific progress take place. The dominant paradigm establishes a research agenda, in which explanatory puzzles are solved by empirical re- search and theorizing within the framework established by the paradigm. When a paradigm becomes dominant it operates rather like a large-scale schema as understood in cognitive psychology (Brewer & Nakamura, 1984). Its network of beliefs fades into the background but, like a schema, continues to shape the thinking and behavior of the scientists who hold it. Clearly, as Kuhn’s analysis im- plies, the creation and imposition of a paradigm are more glorious things than is operating mindlessly within one.

2. Appearance of anomaly. Inevitably, some puzzles prove harder to solve than others, and these are anomalies.

February 1992 • American Psychologist 309

Solving the hard ones wins Nobel prizes, but some puzzles continue to resist solution. Sometimes, recalcitrant puz- zles are shelved, set aside for another day. But others, especially if they are seen as fundamental, may greatly disturb the scientific community and induce a period of crisis.

3. Crisis. If an important anomaly provokes a crisis, the grip of the paradigm on scientists weakens. Its hold will be especially weak on young scientists, as the crisis undermines the normal dogmatism of scientific training. The more brilliant among them—the Einsteins and Hei- senbergs—break out of the confines of the paradigm al- together, rejecting one or more of its defining tenets, pro- posing new ones in their stead. If a new viewpoint is per- suasive—clearing up the anomalies and suggesting fresh lines of investigation—the ancien regime is imperiled.

4. Revolution. Crisis becomes revolution if the ad- herents of the emerging paradigm gain control of the levers of power in science: journal editorships; textbooks; and, today, granting agencies. Followers of the old paradigm may in some cases be able to convert to the new, but often they abandon research to become chairpersons and deans. The old paradigm is replaced by the new, beginning again the cycle of normal science, anomaly, crisis, and revo- lution.

It would be profitless to rehearse the many com- plaints made about Kuhn’s (1962/1970) picture of science and scientific change (Gutting, 1980; Hacking, 1981; Lakatos & Musgrave, 1970). Whatever its faults, it is un- doubtedly appealing, if not always compelling, as in Kuhn’s hands science becomes an intellectual adventure, paradigm making being human creativity at its highest pitch and greatest influence. Perhaps the chief failing of Kuhn’s account was that it offered sketchy examples of revolutions fit to Kuhn’s Procrustean model. To remedy this defect, I. Bernard Cohen (1985) proposed a more empirically based model of scientific revolutions.

/ . Bernard Cohen

Like Kuhn, Cohen (1985) saw revolutions as passing through distinct stages, but unlike Kuhn’s stages, Cohen’s are more precisely defined in terms of ascertainable his- torical occurrences.

1. The revolution in itself. The revolution in itself is the creative phase, in which a scientist or group of scientists proposes a radically new solution to a problem or a radically new theory, sets forth a new framework, or finds a new method of using existing information. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

2. Private commitment. The innovative ideas are committed to paper in notes, diary entries, research log- books, or some other nonpublic form. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

3. The revolution on paper. The new ideas are cir- culated among the members of the scientific community, beginning informally, proceeding to oral presentations, and culminating in publication. During this phase, rev- olutionary ideas are criticized, improved, and polished.

4. Conversion. If it passes the gauntlet of “brutal insistence on demonstration” (Cohen, 1985, p. 35), a rev-

olution becomes a success, converting the majority of sci- entists in a field to its ideas.

More important than his model of stages is Cohen’s (1985) proposal of precise criteria by which to evaluate the claim that an episode in science constituted a revo- lution. Cohen set out four tests:

1. Contemporary testimony. How was the event re- garded by those who experienced it? Scientists must de- scribe experiencing a revolutionary change to their dis- cipline. Cohen regarded this as the major criterion, to be supplemented—but never overridden—by the remaining three.

2. Later documentary history. How was the event treated by later writings in the field? Texts, treatises, and articles must regard the event as revolutionary.

3. Historians’ judgment. How is the event treated by competent historians of the field? To count as a rev- olution, historians must consider it to have been one.

4. Opinion of working scientists. Is the event re- garded by modern scientists as a revolution? Cohen ar- gued that myths of revolution provide important clues to the existence of major changes in science.

It is important to bear in mind the supplementary nature of the final three criteria of revolution. Cohen (1985) refused to recognize as a revolution any event that was not recognized as revolutionary by those who lived through it, regardless of later opinion. Texts, histories, and scientific folklore can only support a claim of revo- lution, but cannot establish one. I apply Cohen’s criteria to claims for revolutions in the brief history of psychology. However, in the case of putative revolutions in psychology, the second and fourth criteria blur together: Too little time has passed since the beginning of psychology to dis- tinguish them, and by and large, the historians of psy- chology have been psychologists themselves.

Roy Porter

In a brief but insightful analysis of revolutions in science, Porter (1986) offered a model of and criteria for evaluating scientific revolutions that distills the essence of Kuhn’s and Cohen’s schemes and emphasizes the parallel to po- litical revolutions. First, “a revolution in science requires overthrow of an entrenched orthodoxy; challenge, resis- tance, struggle and conquest are essentials . . . a new order must be established, a break visible” (p. 300). Sec- ond, “revolutions presuppose both grandeur of scale and urgency of tempo” (p. 300). Third, “it is vital that, at some stage, consciousness should dawn of revolution afoot. The notion of silent or unconscious revolution is next door to nonsense” (p. 300). Finally, “surely scientific revolutions at least must be international” (p. 308).

Conclusion

The models of Kuhn, Cohen, and Porter suggest a series of questions to frame our inquiry into the existence of revolutions in the history of psychology, (a) Was there an old regime of normal science dominated by an “en- trenched orthodoxy”—Kuhn’s paradigm—to be over- thrown? (b) Was the existing paradigm experiencing dif-

310 February 1992 • American Psychologist

ficulties brought on by empirical anomalies demanding solution by radical innovation and the creation of a new worldview? (c) Was there a brief period of intense and acute struggle between proponents of the old regime and the new, and a “break visible” between the old order and the new? (d) Was the alleged revolution international? (e) Was a new regime—paradigm—established?

In answering each question, I apply the empirical criteria for revolutions laid down by Cohen (1985) and Porter (1986), emphasizing, with Cohen, perceptions of revolution by the psychologists involved.

Revolutions in Psychology Although a number of revolutions in psychology have been proposed, including the foundings of experimental psychology by Wundt (Cohen, 1985), of psychoanalysis (Buss, 1978; Michels, 1986), and of humanistic psychol- ogy (Buss), I will restrict myself to consideration of the main story, told earlier, concerning the behaviorist and cognitivist revolutions.

The Behaviorist Revolution

There is unquestionably a widespread movement on foot in which interest is centered in the results of conscious process, rather than in the processes themselves. This is peculiarly true in animal psychology; it is only less true in human psychology. In these cases interest in what may for lack of a better term be called “behavior”; and the analysis of consciousness is primarily justified by the light it throws on behavior, rather than vice versa. (Angell, 1911, p. 47)

According to our reigning mythology, psychology’s first revolution took place when John B. Watson’s be- haviorism overthrew the established paradigm of men- talism. During this revolution, psychology abandoned its first (and traditional) definition as the science of mental life, or consciousness as such, along with its method of introspection, replacing them with a definition of psy- chology as the science of behavior and implementation of its methods of behavior study. I argue that although the changes in psychology that took place in the first de- cades of APA’s life were deep and profound, it is more useful to look on the changes as gradual rather than rev- olutionary.

Did mentalism constitute a paradigm dominating psychology before 1913? Certainly there was general agreement that psychology was primarily the science of consciousness and that its method was introspection, but beyond these very general points there was serious dis- agreement over fundamental, foundational issues.

Consider, first, psychology’s method: introspection. Wundt (1907) was highly critical of the traditional arm- chair introspection used by the philosophers of psychol- ogy’s prescientific past. Essential to his founding of sci- entific psychology was the repudiation of ordinary self- introspection, and its replacement by a new method of experimental introspection (Blumenthal, 1975; Bring- mann & Tweney, 1980; Rieber, 1980). Wundt’s proce- dures involved immediate reports of consciousness under carefully controlled standardized conditions, and Wundt

rigorously insisted on control, replicability, and systematic variability as criteria to be met by any valid experimental procedure. Indeed, many of his techniques would not be regarded today as introspective at all, such as the tachis- toscopic method used to study span of apprehension, later modified by Sperling (1960) in his studies of iconic mem- ory (Leahey, 1981).

William James (1890), on the other hand, insisted that ordinary self-introspection—the very method re- jected by Wundt—was psychology’s essential method for probing consciousness. Although he respected experi- mental results and incorporated them into his Principles of Psychology, it is clear that he found experimentation boring, and in Principles of Psychology he mostly sup- ported his theoretical positions with vivid examples of everyday introspection. Meanwhile, the Wiirzburg psy- chologists, and the later E. B. Titchener (1901 -1905), de- veloped a form of experimental introspection involving the retrospective analysis of remembered consciousness and the generation of long descriptive protocols (Leahey, 1992). Their methods deviated from Wundt’s (1907) cri- teria of strict control and systematic variability, producing eccentric and unrepeatable results, most famously in the imageless thought controversy of the 1910s (Ogden, 1911a, 1911b). There was, in conclusion, no precise agreement among psychologists concerning their scientific method, introspection.

There was also significant disagreement over how psychology should explain its findings. The deepest di- vision concerned the principles governing conscious events. Although Wundt (1896) called the experimental branch of his science “physiological psychology,” he nev- ertheless proposed that mental events were shaped by mental processes governed by mental laws. On the other hand, James (1890) rejected the “Kantian machine-shop” (Vol. 2, p. 275) of the unconscious and the existence of mental forces such as association of ideas. He insisted psychology should be cerebralist and traced conscious events directly to their causes in the nervous system, without postulating intervening mental way stations. Similarly, Titchener (1972) derided Wundt’s hypothes- izing of mental forces and laws, preferring to replace them with motor sensations, and in his last years, he moved to a purely descriptive phenomenology.

These differences over methodology and theory are as deep as any in later psychology. Beyond an agreed- upon definition of psychology as the study of conscious- ness, perforce relying on introspection, everything was disputed. But debates over basic foundational issues characterize preparadigm, not normal science. Had the term been available, it seems likely contemporary psy- chologists would have recognized the presence of com- peting would-be paradigms. In 1898, Titchener distin- guished two approaches to psychology, structural psy- chology and functional psychology, and the ensuing years saw structuralists and functionalists argue for the preem- inence of their point of view (Leahey, 1992). Given the nature and depth of the disputes among the founders of psychology, there was no single paradigmatic ancien re-

February 1992 • American Psychologist 311

gime of mentalism for behaviorism to overthrow revo- lutionarily.

Was mentalism experiencing difficulties brought on by anomalies shortly before 1913? There can be no doubt that the period 1892-1912, especially 1910-1912, was a difficult one for psychology, well attested to by contem- porary witnesses. In his annual report, “Psychological Progress in 1906” in the Psychological Bulletin, E. F. Buchner (1907) noted a “rising tide of dissatisfaction” (p. 1), and in 1911 confessed that many psychologists had become unclear as to what their field was about. The 1910 meeting of the APA (at which Angell delivered the paragraph quoted at the beginning of this section) was dominated by sessions rethinking the definition of psy- chology (Haggerty, 1911). However, the uncertainties of the period 1910-1912 may be viewed not as a prerevo- lutionary crisis, indicating psychology was about to change, but as a dawning consciousness that psychology had already changed. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Anomalies in Kuhn’s (1962/1970) sense of troubling recalcitrant puzzles are hard to find. The imageless thought controversy comes closest to filling the bill, as the tone of the controversy was often sharp and occa- sionally was used to raise basic issues, such as the validity of introspection (Ogden, 1911a, 1911b). However, most articles involved in the debate treated it as a difficult but soluble problem (e.g., Titchener, 1904), and, in any event, behaviorism did not solve the problem of imageless thought, as should happen in a Kuhnian revolution. In- stead, behaviorism declared the problem of imageless thought irrelevant. Psychology’s real anomalies were not Kuhnian empirical puzzles, but difficulties created by broadening psychology to include—in addition to the study of adult human consciousness—animal, child, ab- normal, and clinical psychology. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Was there a brief period of intense crisis and struggle leading to a break visible? Here is the key question, and I will try to show that the important relevant changes in psychology occurred before 1913 and took place in a gradual and largely unnoticed way. The years 1892-1912 defined American psychology as it transformed contin- uously and without break from the study of consciousness to the study of behavior. Space precludes full discussion (see Leahey, 1991, or 1992), but I will sketch as a series of narrowing circles the main forces acting on psychology, showing how the changeover from consciousness to be- havior occurred. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

The largest circle of influence came from American society as it was transforming from an agricultural sea of island communities to an industrial nation state with in- ternational influence (Wiebe, 1967). People migrated from rural communities, ruled by tradition and social control by kith and kin, to industrializing cities that were collections of strangers. New ways of life had to be learned, new skills taught to urban migrants. Led by John Dewey (1900), psychologists recognized the value their discipline might have for creating new means of social adjustment. Focusing on social adjustment meant focusing on behav- ior—most important, learning—and so American social

conditions drew psychologists’ attention away from con- sciousness and toward adjustive behavior. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

In the next circle of influence, developments in psy- chology’s intellectual neighbors reinforced a focus on be- havior. In Darwinian evolution, thoughts not acted on are as of little consequence as thoughts not thought. Psy- chologists, such as Thaddeus Bolton (1902) and H. Heath Bawden (1903, 1904, 1910), argued that perception and consciousness had survival value only if they produced adaptive behavior. Inevitably, the focus of a biologically informed psychology (Angell, 1907) shifted from con- sciousness itself to the fruits of consciousness—behavior. In philosophy, Jamesian pragmatism helped shift psy- chology from concern with consciousness to concern with behavior. Pragmatism—itself a product of Darwinian in- fluence—valued ideas by their concrete consequences, their Jamesian “cash value”; in short, ideas were valued by their effects on behavior.

Finally, within psychology itself, research problems and theoretical issues undercut the primacy of conscious- ness. The research problem leading the way to behavior study involved comparative psychology. Animal psy- chology had begun as the study of animal mind, but be- came bogged down on the question of what behaviors permitted one to attribute mental events and processes to animals, because they are incapable of introspection. Various criteria of mentality were offered, but none seemed adequate (Watson, 1907). Merely raising the question shifted attention to behavior from the con- sciousness lurking ghostlike behind it, and at least one animal psychologist had concluded by 1908 that behavior could be studied independently of any translation into mentalese (Swartz, 1908; Watson, 1909). Similar devel- opments took place in abnormal and child psychology (Sanford, 1903) and in clinical psychology, whose main tool, the mental test, was not introspective (Cattell, 1904).

On the theoretical side, it was becoming unclear what, if anything, consciousness contributes to motor re- sponse. Specifically, building on Jamesian foundations, the motor theory of consciousness moved consciousness to a peripheral position in the work of behavior adjust- ment. The motor theory of consciousness began with James’s observations on the determination of conscious content by one’s responses to stimuli, most familiarly ex- pressed in the James-Lange theory of emotion. As John Dewey (1896), and even the arch introspectionist Hugo Munsterberg (Hale, 1980), developed the theory, con- sciousness was increasingly seen as an observer of behav- ior, rather than as an actor that causes behavior. The mo- tor theory of consciousness implied that study of con- sciousness was something of an intellectual luxury, because what counted in Darwinian evolution and social change was how organisms adjust their behavior to changing circumstances.

The upshot of all of these developments was the sit- uation described by Angell (1911) at the 1910 meeting of the APA. Reporting to philosophers, M. E. Haggerty (1911) noted that at the 1910 meeting no one defended the traditional definition of psychology as the study of

312 February 1992 • American Psychologist

consciousness. For a host of reasons psychologists had moved in the direction of studying behavior, although Angell’s phrase “for lack of a better word” suggests how difficult it was for psychologists to recognize and label the change their field had undergone.

Psychology, then, moved almost without notice from the science of mental life to the science of behavior in the two decades preceding 1913. No innovation or cluster of innovations caused the change. Instead, one finds the gradual shaping of a field by a combination of social, intellectual, and indigenous forces. Never was there a break visible, an awareness of making a revolution. Even in his behaviorist manifesto, Watson (1913) does not use the term revolution, although the word had been applied to science by Fontenelle, Lavoisier, and by Darwinians (Cohen, 1985) well before 1913. Nor was the response to Watson’s article one of rejection and resistance (Samelson, 1981). Nor, in the aftermath, did Watson in his auto- biography (Watson, 1936/1961) boast of making a rev- olution. Contemporary observers, such as Jastrow (1927), Woodworth (1924), and Williams (1931), said Watson’s angry rhetoric and extreme muscle twitchism created but the illusion of novelty; only compared with the subjective introspective techniques of the Wiirzburgers and Titch- ener—which the founding introspectionist, Wundt (1907), excoriated—did behaviorism seem new. As a psychologist, Watson was as good at public relations as he would be later as an ad man. He created smoke, but there was no fire.

Was behaviorism an international revolution? Sci- ence is supposed to constitute an international commu- nity, so revolutions in science, because they change the field, should be international in scope. However, even proponents of the concept of a behavioral revolution con- cede that behaviorism was largely an American phenom- enon (Baars, 1986).

Conclusion. The conclusion best supported by the evidence is that psychology experienced no behaviorist revolution in 1913. Introspective psychology did not constitute a paradigm to be overthrown, and although psychology did change in the years before 1913, the changes were gradual and only dimly perceived and did not occur in response to empirical anomalies demanding radical solution. Behaviorial psychology emerged contin- uously—if rapidly—out of introspective psychology, and the so-called revolution constituted recognition of change rather than making change. The last question, whether behaviorism constituted a new paradigm, is the first question to ask of the “cognitive revolution.”

The Cognitive Revolution

Le theme d’une revolution cognitive en psychologie, qui em- prunte sa terminologie a la theorie des revolutions scientifiques de Kuhn, est aujourd’hui devenu banal [The theme of a cognitive revolution in psychology, which borrows its terminology from the theory of scientific revolutions of Kuhn, has today become banal]. (Legrand, 1990, p. 248)

Belief in a cognitive revolution is an entrenched part of modern psychology’s form of life. However, I will press

the case that there is even less to the alleged cognitive revolution than to the alleged behaviorist revolution. By 1913, psychology had indeed changed deeply, albeit not in a revolutionary fashion. The very subject matter of psychology had changed from the description and expla- nation of consciousness to the description, prediction, control, and explanation of behavior, as Angell appears to have been the first to notice. I shall call the psychology described by Angell behavioralism (Leahey, 1992), to distinguish it from introspective mentalism, reserving be- haviorism to refer to the specific schools of behavior study that flourished from about 1930 to 1960. My central ar- guments will be that these various behaviorisms did not constitute a paradigm and that cognitive psychology rep- resents the continued development of behavioralist psy- chology.

Did behaviorism constitute a paradigm dominating psychology after 1913? Certainly behaviorism brought an end to the lush excesses of Wiirzburg and late Titch- enerian introspection, but it did not expunge the exper- imental psychology of consciousness. Practically speaking, what Wundt inaugurated was the scientific study of sen- sation and perception, including processes such as atten- tion. Although after 1910 such studies no longer occupied center stage in psychology—being overshadowed by re- search on behavior, especially learning—they did not dis- appear (Davis & Gould, 1929; Lovie 1983). The central work of mentalistic psychology continued, but it was no longer thought of as the study of consciousness.

Psychology after 1913 still looked preparadigmatic. As the behavioral movement proceeded, contemporary observers, such as Hunter (1922) and Woodworth (1924), recognized that there was no single enterprise called be- haviorism beyond the general commitment to behavior study. Although the definition of psychology had changed from the study of consciousness to the study of behavior, psychologists remained as divided as ever over the foun- dations of their field.

For example, consider a metatheoretical issue as foundational as any a science might debate: What should be the fundamental explanatory terms in its theoretical vocabulary? Should psychology regard consciousness as outside the scope of psychology because it is private (the view of methodological behaviorism), or should it be in- cluded in scientific psychology because science must ex- plain everything (the view of Lashley’s, 1923, strict be- haviorism) and because consciousness can influence be- havior (the view of radical behaviorism; Skinner, 1957)? Should we look to neurophysiology for our theoretical framework (Lashley, 1923)? Should we postulate inter- vening variables coming between stimulus and response (the view of Tolman, Hull, and mediational psychology; Leahey, 1991, 1992), or should they be shunned as in- vitations to pseudoscientific myth making (Skinner, 1953). If we do allow intervening variables, how should we construe them? Should we regard them as placeholders for physiological processes, as Hull did (Smith, 1986)? Should they be interpreted realistically (Leahey, 1992) as referents to real but unconscious mental states, as Tolman

February 1992 • American Psychologist 313

did (Smith)? Or, finally, should they be construed instru- mentalistically (Leahey, 1992) as fictions operationally defined, having no surplus meaning beyond the obser- vations they organize, as argued by MacCorquodale and Meehl (1948) and Kendler (1952)?

Because fighting over such issues has seldom, if ever, ceased in psychology, psychologists may take it to be part of “normal” science. However, according to Kuhn (1962/ 1970), it is precisely these kinds of debates that acceptance of a paradigm is supposed to settle. If a discipline, such as psychology, debates foundational questions, it is not in a period of normal science; if a movement, such as behaviorism, debates foundational questions, it is not a paradigm. There was, therefore, no paradigmatic ancien regime of behaviorism for cognitive psychology to over- throw revolutionarily.

Was behaviorism experiencing difficulties brought on by anomalies in 1951-1956? Writing in 1971, David Palermo, participant writing as historian, said that psy- chology was only “ripe” for revolution. But 15 years later, Baars (1986) and Gardner (1985) in their books on the cognitive revolution located its metaphorical conception in 1948 at the Hixon Symposium on Cerebral Mecha- nisms in Behavior (Jeffress, 1951), and its metaphorical birthdate at September 11, 1956 (G. Miller, 1979) during the Symposium on Information Theory at the Massa- chusetts Institute of Technology (MIT). The Hixon sym- posium is best known for Lashley’s famous paper on the problem of serial order in behavior (Lashley, 1951); at MIT, the key presentations were by Newell and Simon on their pioneering work building a thinking computer program and by Chomsky on the inadequacy of existing theories of language (Gardner, 1985). Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

It is not obvious, however, that the birth of cognitive psychology owed anything to empirical anomalies de- manding innovation in order to solve them. Under the influence of Kuhn, Palermo (1971), writing when the question was still “Is [italics added] a scientific revolution taking place” (p. 135), proposed a list of anomalies, be- ginning with the finding that children’s discrimination learning differed from that of animals (Kuenne, 1946). But the anomalies listed by Palermo had already aided the creation of “liberalized S-R [stimulus-response] the- ory” (N. Miller, 1959), in which chains of covert stimulus- response connections were said to mediate between ex- ternal stimuli and overt responses, especially in humans, and mediational theories were going strong in the early 1960s. Although Palermo tried to find in mediational theories—especially Kendler and Kendler (1962)—cracks in behaviorism, they are not readily apparent in the ar- ticles themselves or in the statements of the mediational theorists (including Kendler, 1952) interviewed by Baars (1986). Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Moreover, neither Baars (1986) nor Gardner (1985)—the leading historiographical advocates of the cognitive revolution—discussed any supposed anomalies. Baars interviewed many participants in the “revolution,” from old-line behaviorists to young, iconoclastic, cognitive scientists. Almost all of them discussed how good exper-

iments and solid data advanced the cause of cognitive psychology, but none drew attention to Kuhnian anom- alies. The pattern that emerges from the interviews is not one of insoluble anomalies stumbled on by behaviorists and triumphantly solved by cognitivists, but of experi- ments invented by psychologists already committed to cognitivism and used rhetorically to persuade others.

To the degree that malaise and unhappiness existed during the critical years of cognitivism’s gestation and infancy—and one cannot deny that they existed—they involved amorphous disquiet about psychological theory and a vague worry that S-R theories possessed serious shortcomings, especially with regard to human behavior. Certainly some psychologists were eager to proclaim a crisis (Koch, 1951), but others—perhaps most—thought that a reformed S-R theory (N. Miller, 1959; Osgood, 1956) or a purified behaviorism (Skinner, 1950) would carry the behavioral movement progressively forward. Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

Indeed, the major causes and supports of the revival of cognitive psychology came from outside psychology itself. Although Lashley (1951) was a psychologist, he spoke as a physiologist in his Hixon symposium paper. Newell (1973) and Simon (1990) pursued and originally published their work outside psychology, in economics and computer science. Chomsky was a linguist who had happened to encounter psychologists. Psychology did not get its own influential statement of cognitive science until Neisser’s 1967 text, Cognitive Psychology. Most impor- tant, the leading theory in cognitive psychology, infor- mation processing, was taken over from computer science. As in the period 1892-1912, the pressures making for change in psychology between 1948 and 1956 arose not from internal, technical failures of psychological research, but were conceptual, primarily driven by forces outside psychology.

Was there a brief period of intense crisis and struggle leading to a break visible? The evidence here is conflict- ing, but adds up to an interesting although not prerevo- lutionary picture. Gardner (1985) never advanced a case for revolution, but calmly narrated the continuous de- velopment of cognitive psychology from its Cartesian roots to the present, with remarkably little reference to behaviorism or conflict between it and cognitivism. Baars (1986) wrote, “Between 1955 and 1965 a quiet revolution in thought took place in scientific psychology . . . the cognitive shift was not self-conscious.. . . Experimental psychologists did not set out to make a revolution” (p. 141). Nor was the existence of a revolution acknowledged by most of those he interviewed. If we accept his (and Gardner’s) dates for the revolution, it fails the key evi- dentiary test of recognition by contemporaries.

On the other hand, in 1971, Palermo sensed crisis and incipient revolution. In 1968, Horton and Dixon, too, felt a “revolution is certainly in the making” (p. 580). Robert E. Shaw (1986) described the Center for Human Learning at the University of Minnesota as a center of revolution after 1965. Baars (1986) wrote, “The under- standing of the cognitive revolution followed the event” (p. 141).

314 February 1992 • American Psychologist

What accounts for these differences of opinion? There are various possible explanations, of course, but I think the right one is suggested by James J. Jenkins, who ran the Center for Learning at the University of Minnesota in the years of supposed revolution. Jenkins told Baars (1986), “And, of course, everybody toted around their little copy of Kuhn’s The structure of scientific revolu- tions” (p. 249).

Jenkins’s testimony suggested that there was no awareness of revolution until Kuhn’s book suggested it. Its publication in 1962 colored an era (Coleman & Sal- amon, 1988) and itself provided a justification for the “revolution” (Peterson, 1981). Especially for graduate students learning the (boring) tools of their profession, the high romantic drama and intellectual adventure of revolution making and the joy of breaking behaviorist crockery must have been much more appealing than the day-to-day mundaneness of normal science. I was in graduate school at the University of Illinois from 1970 to 1974 and was always told by William F. Brewer that a revolution was going on. The present article started as a dissenting class paper that I wrote for him.

In the period after 1965, as in the period 1892-1912, the larger social environment played an important role. The 1960s were the days of drugs and protest and of the revolution smashing the intellectual crockery of Western civilization and the actual glass of the ruling class (Collier & Horowitz, 1989). Participating in a scientific revolution at the same time as a political one unified personal and professional lives, heightened the romantic sense of mak- ing epochal change, and made the changing times that much more exciting. Surely, it was satisfying to attack tenured old fogies, supported by a scholarly reference to “Kuhn, 1962.”

Thus, there was no experienced disciplinary struggle in the revolutionary era identified by Baars (1986) and Gardner (1985), but there was after 1965, created by Kuhn’s (1962/1970) book in a sort of self-fulfilling prophecy. It is also hard to identify any moment of a break visible between behaviorism and cognitivism. If G. Miller (1979) is right that cognitive science was born Sep- tember 11, 1956, it is a break visible only with 20-20 hindsight. In any event, a revolution drawn out from 1948 to at least 1971 is no revolution; as Porter (1986) wrote, “Long revolutions are terminological abuses” (p. 300).

Was the cognitive revolution international? George Miller told Baars (1986) about a talk he gave at Oxford University in 1963, in which he “lambasted the hell out of the behaviorists” (p. 212) to a puzzled audience, be- cause, as he found later that there were only three be- haviorists in England, none of whom were present. Be- cause behaviorism was not international, the cognitive revolution could not have been international. It must be acknowledged, though, that information-processing psy- chology has had world-wide influence, perhaps because of the international influence of its metaphorical base, the computer.

Did the cognitive revolution create a new paradigm and inaugurate an era of normal science? In 1971, Pal-

ermo did not correctly foresee the direction psychology would take. He thought that Chomsky’s revolution in linguistics would bequeath a rationalist paradigm to psy- cholinguistics and thence to experimental psychology as a whole. Instead, the main form taken by cognitive science was the information-processing paradigm, rooted in the computer metaphor. It was introduced to psychology mainly by Neisser (1967) in his Cognitive Psychology, and then self-consciously enshrined as the new Kuhnian par- adigm for psychology by Lachman, Lachman, and But- terfield (1979). Although some psychologists today, such as Neisser (1976) himself, wish it were not so, informa- tion-processing psychology is the mainstream in experi- mental psychology. Two questions then pose themselves: Is information processing a Kuhnian paradigm, and is information processing a form of behavioralism or gen- uinely something new?

A paradigm, in Kuhn’s (1962/1970) revised scheme has two components, the shared exemplar and the dis- ciplinary matrix. The shared exemplar is close to what scientists call a paradigm, being an ideal model of re- search. In the case of information processing, however, a recognized problem has been the proliferation of research paradigms. It is virtually the case that small research teams each have their own experimental paradigm, mak- ing it very difficult to assemble a general picture of the human cognitive architecture (Estes, 1991; Newell, 1973; Simon, 1990).

The disciplinary matrix consists of a shared set of metatheoretical, philosophical, and metaphysical beliefs that determine n normal science -eommuaity’-s form -of life. As I have tried to show, psychology has had a difficult time establishing agreement on foundational issues. Both introspective psychology and the behavioralism that fol- lowed were defined by only the vaguest commitments to the nature of psychological science. So it remains with information-processing psychology. It is agreed that or- ganisms take in information from the environment; pro- cess it internally, creating representations; make decisions based on represented information; and in consequence, behave.

Such a characterization would not exclude Tolman (1932) from cognitive science. Nor would it necessarily exclude the mediational S-R theorists of liberalized S-R theory, if covert responses are counted as representations and the formation of mediating connections is counted as processing. Indeed, it was from the ranks of mediational psychologists and their students that many of the early cognitivists sprang (Baars, 1986; Kessel, 1986; Leahey, 1992). Moreover, there is good reason to regard cognitiv- ism as a new form of behavioralism that is based on the computer metaphor but aimed at the description, pre- diction, and control of behavior.

For example, Ericsson and Simon (1980) wanted to achieve “processing models so explicit that they could actually produce the predicted behavior from the infor- mation in the stimulus” (p. 215), which perfectly echoed Watson’s (1913) goal for psychology: “In a system of psy- chology completely worked out, given the response the

February 1992 • American Psychologist 315

stimuli can be predicted; given the stimuli the response can be predicted” (p. 167). Or consider cognitive psy- chology’s attitude toward consciousness. Nisbett and Wilson (1977) dismissed introspective reports as of es- sentially no value in constructing and testing theories of cognitive processes, nor do they even entertain the no- tion—central to psychology’s founders—that cognitive psychology ought to attempt to explain why people have the experiences they do, even apart from their possible causal effects, or lack thereof, on behavior (Tulving, 1989). George Mandler is often considered one of cognitive psy- chology’s more radical thinkers, but in conversation with Baars (1986) he denned modern psychology as any meth- odological behaviorist would:

Psychology must talk about people. Your private experience is a theoretical construct to me. I have no direct access to your private experience. I do have direct access to your behavior. In that sense I’m a behaviorist. In that sense, everybody is a be- haviorist today, (p. 256)

And that sense of psychology is behavioralism, as defined byAngellin 1910.

Conclusion. The coming of cognitive psychology is best regarded, not as the revolutionary creation of a new paradigm slaying the older one of behaviorism, but as the appearance of a new form of behavioralism based on a new technology, the computer. By the 1950s, mediational S-R behaviorists were already looking for ways to rep- resent internal processing of stimuli, and the computer metaphor provided a better language than mediational r-s notation did. Moreover, the existence of artificial in- telligence—the manufacture of information-processing devices behaving intelligently and purposively—bolstered faith in mediating mental processes by showing they could be embodied in material devices rather than immaterial souls (J. Miller, 1983). Information-processing psychol- ogy, no less than any form of historical behaviorism, aims at the description, prediction, control, and explanation of behavior, without any special attention being given to conscious experience (Tulving, 1989). Perhaps during the feverish days of the 1960s, another, less behavioral, road might have been taken—but it was not taken, at least not by the main body of experimental psychologists. The mainstream of psychology in 1992 remains as firmly be- havioralistic as it was in 1910.

Conclusion: Who Needs Revolutions? In the 1930s, psychologists, ever uncertain about their status as scientists, adopted logical positivism’s philosophy of science as a recipe for making psychological science. Doing so, they distorted their perceptions of their own leading theorists, Hull and Tolman (Smith, 1986), and forced psychology onto the Procrustean bed of logical positivism (Leahey, 1980, 1983). Later on, it emerged that logical positivism was bad philosophy of science (Suppe, 1977), but the damage was done. If I am right about psychology’s history, then we might conclude, as- suming that Kuhn’s (1962/1970) analysis is correct, that psychology is not a science, because it has had no normal

science and hence no revolutions. But we need not assume that Kuhn is good philosophy of science, and instead res- cue psychology from the Procrustean bed of Kuhnianism. His various theses have been roundly criticized (Suppe, 1977), and the trend in history and philosophy of science today, excepting Cohen, is toward emphasizing continuity and development instead of revolution. In the revised edition of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962/ 1970), Kuhn retracted many of his more controversial and radical proposals, although many psychologists re- main unaware of it (Coleman & Salamon, 1988). More- over, Cohen’s account of revolutions is less philosophical and more empirical than Kuhn’s, and the revolution he assigns to psychology is plausibly genuine: its innovative founding by Wundt and James. Moving away from Kuhn, some historians (e.g., Hull, 1988a, 1988b; Shrader, 1980) want to impose on history of science a model based on biological evolution extending the Darwinian process of mutation and natural selection from organisms to ideas. However, having rescued psychology from positivism and Kuhn, I do not want to force it onto the bed of evolu- tionary epistemology.

In place of a story of revolutions, one can tell psy- chology’s story as a narrative of research traditions (Lau- dan, 1977; Maclntyre, 1977, 1981), changing over time in a framework of pairs of metatheoretical commitments called themata (Holton, 1973). Some of the important psychological themata would be molar-molecular, rep- resentationalism-realism, mentalism-reductionism, and rules-connections. Some of the developing traditions would be representational psychology, running from Locke through Tolman to information-processing psy- chology; realist psychology, running from the Scottish realists through the American neo-realists, to the early Tolman, Gibson, and radical behaviorism; connectionist psychology, running from the British associationists through Titchener, Thorndike, Hull, neo-Hullians, and today’s connectionists; and reductive psychology, running from La Mettrie (fitfully) through parts of Wundt, Titch- ener, James, and Freud, briefly emerging aggressively in Lashley, and reviving today with Churchland (1987).

Each tradition has progressed. The representations posited by cognitive science are more sophisticated than Locke’s idea or Tolman’s cognitive map. The analyses of behavior by contemporary radical behaviorists are more precise and robust than Skinner’s own. The neural net- works of contemporary connectionism have advanced past traditional laws of association or S-R bonds to mathematically characterized state spaces. In the decade of the brain, of course, neurophysiological research is quantum leaps ahead of Lashley’s pioneering search for the engram. Save for Wundt’s founding of psychology, revolution in psychology is a myth.

REFERENCES

Angell, J. R. (1907). The province of functional psychology. Psychological Review, 14,61-91.

Angell, J. R. (1911). Philosophical and psychological usage of the terms mind, consciousness, and soul. Psychological Bulletin, 8, 46-47.

316 February 1992 • American Psychologist

Baars, B. J. (1986). The cognitive revolution in psychology. New \brk: Guilford Press.

Bawden, H. H. (1903). The functional theory of parallelism. Philosoph- ical Review, 72,299-319.

Bawden, H. H. (1904). The meaning of the psychical in functional psy- chology. Philosophical Review, 13, 298-319.

Bawden, H. H. (1910). Mind as a category of psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 7, 221-225.

Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (1990). Connectionism and the mind. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

Blumenthal, A. (1975). A reappraisal of Wilhelm Wundt. American Psychologist, 30, 1081-1088.

Bolton, T. (1902). A biological view of perception. Psychological Review, 9, 537-548.

Brewer, W. R, & Nakamura, G. V. (1984). The nature and function of schemas. In R. S. Wyer & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (Vol. I, pp. 119-160). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Bringmann, W. G., & Tweney, R. D. (1980). (Eds.). Wundt studies. To- ronto, Canada: Hogrefe.

Brinton, C. (1952). The anatomy of revolution. New York: Vintage. Buchner, E. F. (1907). Psychological progress in 1906. Psychological

Bulletin, 4, 1-9.

Bulletin, 8, 1-10. Buss, A. R. (1978). The structure of psychological revolutions. Journal

of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 14, 57-64. Butterfield, H. (1957). The origins of modem science, 1300-1800 (rev.

ed.) New York: Free Press. (Original work published 1949) Cattell, J. M. (1904). The conceptions and methods of psychology. Pop-

ular Science Monthly, 66, 176-186. Churchland, P. S. (1987). Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Clark, J. C. D. (1986). Revolution and rebellion, state and society in

England in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

Cohen, I. B. (1985). Revolution in science. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

Coleman, S. R., & Salamon, R. (1988). Kuhn’s Structure of scientific revolutions in the psychological journal literature, 1969-1983: A de- scriptive study. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 9, 415-445.

Collier, P., & Horowitz, D. (1989). Destructive generation: Second thoughts about the sixties. New \brk: Summit.

Davis, R., & Gould, S. E. (1929). Changing tendencies in general psy- chology. Psychological Review, 36, 320-331.

Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex-arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3, 357-370.

Dewey, J. (1900). Psychology and social practice. Psychological Review, 4, 27-53.

Ericsson, K. A., & Simon, H. A. (1980). Verbal reports as data. Psycho- logical Review, 87, 215-251.

Estes, W. K. (1991). Cognitive architectures from the standpoint of an experimental psychologist. Annual Review of Psychology, 42, 1-28.

Gardner, H. (1985). The mind’s new science: A history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Basic Books.

Griewank, K. (1969/1971). Emergence of the concept of revolution. In C. Paynton & R. Blackey (Eds.), Why revolutions? Theories and anal- yses (pp. 16-22). Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.

Gutting, G. (1980). (Ed.). Paradigms and revolutions: Applications and appraisals of Thomas Kuhn’s philosophy of science. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

Hacking, I. (1981). (Ed.). Scientific revolutions. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

Haggerty, M. E. (1911). The nineteenth annual meeting of the A.P.A. Journal of Philosophy, 8, 204-217.

Hale, M. (1980). Human science and social order. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Holton, G. (1973). Thematic origins of scientific thought, Kepler to Ein- stein. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Horton, D. L., & Dixon, T. R. (1968). Tradition, trends, and inno- vations. In T. R. Dixon & D. L. Horton (Eds.), Verbal behavior and general behavior theory (pp. 572-580). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Hull, D. (1988a). A mechanism and its metaphysics: An evolutionary

account of the social and conceptual development of science. Biology and Philosophy, 3, 123-155.

Hull, D. (1988b). Science as a process: An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Hunter, W. S. (1922). An open letter to the anti-behaviorists. Journal of Philosophy, 19, 307-308.

James, W. (1890). Principles of psychology. New York: Holt. Jastrow, J. (1927). The reconstruction of psychology. Psychological Re-

view, 34, 169-195. Jeffress, L. A. (1951). (Ed.). Cerebral mechanisms in behavior. New

York: Wiley. Kendler, H. H. (1952). “What is learned?”—A theoretical blind alley.

Psychological Review, 59, 269-277′. Kendlei; H. H., & Kendler, T. S. (1962). Horizontal and vertical processes

in problem solving. Psychological Review, 36, 471-490. Kessel, F. (1986, August). Cognitive psychology reconsidered: What hap-

pened to the revolution? Symposium presented at the 94th Annual Convention of the American Psychological Association, Washington, DC.

Koch, S. (1951). Theoretical psychology, 1950: An overview. Psycholog-

‘ Kuenne.’MT K. (1946). Experimental investigation of the relation of language to transposition behavior in young children. Journal of Ex- perimental Psychology, 36, 471-490.

Kuhn, T. S. (1957). The Copernican revolution. New York: Vintage. Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (Rev. ed). Chi-

cago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1962) Lachman, R., Lachman, J., & Butterfield, E. (1979). Cognitive psy-

chology and information processing. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Lakatos, I., & Musgrave, A. (1970). (Eds.). Criticism and the growth

of knowledge. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Lashley, K. S. (1923). The behavioristic interpretation of conscious-

ness. Psychological Review, 30, 237-272, 329-353. Lashley, K. S. (1951). The problem of serial order in behavior. In L.

A. Jeffress (Ed.), Cerebral mechanisms in behavior (pp. 112-136). New York: Wiley.

Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Leahey, T. H. (1980). The myth of operationism. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 1, 127-143.

Leahey, T. H. (1981). The mistaken mirror: On Wundt’s and Titch- ener’s psychologies. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sci- ences, 17, 273-282.

Leahey, T. H. (1983). Operationism and ideology: Reply to Kendler. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 4, 81-90.

Leahey, T. H. (1991). A history of modern psychology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Leahey, T. H. (1992). A history of psychology (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Legrand, M. (1990). Du behaviorisme au cognitivisme [From behav- iorism to cognitivism]. L’Annee Psychologique, 90, 247-286.

Lovie, A. D. (1983). Attention and behaviourism: Fact and fiction. British Journal of Psychology, 74, 301-310.

MacCorquodale, K., & Meehl, P. (1948). On a distinction between hy- pothetical constructs and intervening variables. Psychological Review, 55, 95-107.

Maclntyre, A. (1977). Epistemological crises, dramatic narrative, and the philosophy of science. The Monist, 60, 453-471.

Maclntyre, A. (1981). After virtue. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

Michels, R. (1986). How psychoanalysis changes. Journal of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis, 14, 285-295.

Miller, G. (1979, June 1). A very personal history. Talk presented at the Cognitive Science Workshop, MIT, Cambridge, MA.

Miller, J. (1983). States of mind. New York: Pantheon. Miller, N. (1959). Liberalization of basic S-R concepts. In S. Koch (Ed.),

Psychology: Study of a science (Vol. 2, pp. 196-292). New York: McGraw-Hill.

Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. New York: Appleton-Century- Crofts.

Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality. San Francisco: Freeman.

February 1992 • American Psychologist 317

Newell, A. (1973). You can’t play 20 questions with nature and win. In W. G. Chase (Ed.), Visual information processing (pp. 283-308). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231- 259.

Ogden, R. M. (1911a). Imageless thought. Psychological Bulletin, 8, 183- 197.

Ogden, R. M. (1911b). The unconscious biases of laboratories. Psycho- logical Bulletin, 8, 330-331.

Osgood, C. E. (1956). Behavior theory and the social sciences. Behavioral Science, 1, 167-185.

Palermo, D. (1971). Is a scientific revolution taking place in psychology? Science Studies. 1, 135-155.

Peterson, G. L. (1981). Historical self-understanding in the social sciences: The use of Thomas Kuhn in psychology. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 11, 1-30.

Paynton, C. T, & Blackey, R. (1971). (Eds.). Why revolution? Theories and analyses. Cambridge, MA: Schenkman.

Porter, R. (1986). The scientific revolution, a spoke in the wheel? In R. Porter & M. Teich (Eds.), Revolutions in history (pp. 290-316). Cam- bridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

Porter, R., & Teich, M. (1986). (Eds.). Revolutions in history. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

Rieber, R. W.(1980). (Ed.). Wilhelm Wundt and the making of a scientific psychology. New York: Plenum.

Samelson, F. (1981). Struggle for scientific authority: The reception of Watson’s behaviorism, 1913-1920. Journal of the History of the Be- havioral Sciences, 17, 399-425.

Sanford, E. C. (1903). Psychology and physics. Psychological Review, 10, 105-119.

Schneider, W. (1987). Connectionism: Is a paradigm shift taking place? Behavior Research Methods, Instruments, and Computers, 19, 73- 83.

Shaw, R. E. (1986, August). The cognitive psychology revolution: A per- sonal perspective. Paper presented at the 94th Annual Convention of the American Psychological Association, Washington, DC.

Shrader, D. (1980). The evolutionary development of science. Review of Metaphysics, 34, 273-296.

Simon, H. A. (1990). Invariants of human behavior. Annual Review of Psychology, 41, 1-20.

Skinner, B. F. (1950). Are theories of learning necessary? Psychological Review, 57, 196-215.

Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New \brk: Macmillan.

Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-Century- Crofts.

Smith, L. S. (1986). Behaviorism and logical positivism: A revised account of the alliance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presen- tations. Psychological Monographs, 74 (11, Whole No. 498).

Suppe, F. (1977). (Ed.). The structure of scientific theories. Urbana: Uni- versity of Illinois Press.

Swartz, C. K. (1908). The scientific association of Johns Hopkins Uni- versity. Science, 28, 814-815.

Tienson, J. (1991). An introduction to connectionism. In J. L. Garfield (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive science: The essential readings (pp. 381-397). New York: Paragon House.

Titchener, E. B. (1901-1905). Experimental psychology: A manual of laboratory practice (A vols.). New York: Macmillan.

Titchener, E. B. (1904). Lectures on the experimental psychology of the thought processes. New York: Macmillan.

Titchener, E. B. (1972). Systematic psychology: Prolegomena. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive behavior in animals and men. New York: Century.

Tulving, E. (1989). Memory, performance, knowledge, and experi- ence. European Journal of Psychology, 1, 3-26.

Watson, J. B. (1907). Comparative psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 4, 288-302.

Watson, J. B. (1909). A point of view in comparative psychology. Psy- chological Bulletin, 6, 57-58.

Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20, 158-177.

Watson, J. B. (1961). John Broadus Watson. In C. Murchison (Ed.), History of psychology in autobiography (Vol. 3, pp. 271-281). New York: Russell & Russell. (Original work published 1936)

Wiebe, R. (1967). The search for order, 1877-1920. New York: Hill & Wang.

Williams, K. (1931). Five behaviorisms. American Journal of Psychology, 43, 337-361.

Woodworth, R. S. (1924). Four varieties of behaviorism. Psychological Review, 31, 257-264.

Wundt, W. M. (1896). Lectures on human and animal psychology. New York: Macmillan.

Wundt, W. M. (1907). Uber Ausfrageexperimente und iiber die Methoden zur Psychologie des Denkens [Concerning interroga- tion—Experiments and methods for the psychology of thought]. Psychologische Studien, 3, 301-360.

318 February 1992 • American Psychologist

Hire a competent writer to help you with

Discuss some of the proposals regarding Psychology’s status as a science and its problems regarding methodology and epistemology.

troublesome homework